“We are our memories” it is often said. Remembering is
something each of us does on a daily basis in several ways and for several
reasons. We can “remember” things we have to do on a particular day. Or we can
remember past events that either involve us or not.
Today we will tackle cases of remembering past events in which we are not personally involved but in which our remembering may be quite important. Such a case is the case of witnessing. Witnessing has particular importance in the juridical domain, when people are asked to give their description of an event that they assisted, in order to resolve in court “what really happened” during this event. What witnesses attest is really crucial, for their claims play a role in the final decision of the court. But how accurate are the attestations of witnesses? And how accurate can they be?
Today we will tackle cases of remembering past events in which we are not personally involved but in which our remembering may be quite important. Such a case is the case of witnessing. Witnessing has particular importance in the juridical domain, when people are asked to give their description of an event that they assisted, in order to resolve in court “what really happened” during this event. What witnesses attest is really crucial, for their claims play a role in the final decision of the court. But how accurate are the attestations of witnesses? And how accurate can they be?
Elisabeth
Loftus and her colleagues have run a long series of studies, for over 30 years
now, showing the ease with which the witnesses’ memories can be influenced and
crucially distorted. In a set of psychological experiments (Loftus, 1975) she
asked university students to watch short film clips of a specific incident and
then asked them several questions about this incident. The goal was to see how
asking specific questions can modify and distort people’s memories of the event
they had watched.
In one study (Loftus, 1975,
experiment 2) the clip was an extract from a film displaying eight demonstrators entering into a
class and disrupting it. After a noisy confrontation the demonstrators finally
left the classroom. The participants of the study were split in two groups.
Both groups received a questionnaire on the incident after they had watched the
clip. And there was only one question in those questionnaires that was different
for the two groups. The first group was asked “Was the leader of the four demonstrators who entered the
classroom a male?” The second group was asked “Was the leader of the twelve demonstrators who entered the
classroom a male?” As you may have
noticed, there is a particularity about these two questions; that is they presuppose something that is wrong.
Presupposition is a very interesting mechanism on which we are very often based
when we use language. It consists in the fact that in linguistic communication
we implicitly stick to conditions that must hold for our statements to be
appropriate in a specific context, and thus make sense. To make things clearer,
imagine that I tell you “The past two years that I have been living in Brussels
have been magnificent!”. In this case I presuppose that I am living in Brussels and, that I have been doing so for
two years. If for the past two years I have lived in Berlin, then my statement does
not make sense and is obviously false. Now, importantly, presuppositions also
play a role when we ask questions. When I ask you what is the name of your cat,
then I presuppose that you have a cat. If you don’t, my presupposition is false
in this context and my question does not make sense if addressed to you. Coming
back to the two questions that the students in Loftus’ experiment were asked,
they are both based on a false presupposition: the first one presupposes that
the demonstrators were four, and the second one that they were twelve. The
actual demonstrators were eight! So let’s see, what these false presuppositions
can do on people’s memory of the incident they have watched with their own
eyes. When participants came back to the psychology lab one week later they
were asked again multiple questions concerning the incident they had watched,
among which a simple one: “How many demonstrators did you see entering the
classroom?”. All participants had watched the same clip –meaning that they had
seen eight demonstrators. Yet, surprisingly, the two groups had been influenced
by this one question with the false presupposition they had been asked one week
ago. People asked about twelve demonstrators answered on average that there
were 8.85 demonstrators, while people asked about four demonstrators answered
that there were 6.40 demonstrators. This difference may look small, but
statistical analyses show that it is significant. This means that it can not be
due to chance, but that it is an effect of the different question that the two
groups had been asked after watching the incident.
These
results are interesting because they show how our memory of an incident we have
witnessed with our own eyes can be influenced by information that we receive
after we have assisted at the event. The most intriguing element, is the way in
which this information can be implanted in people’s minds. Participants in the
above-described study were not directly told that the number of demonstrators
in the clip they had watched was four or twelve. This information was indirectly
suggested to them just because they were asked a question that could not hold
if the false presupposed information (the false number of demonstrators) was
not correct. And this indirectly suggested information was somehow integrated
in their representation of the event. This, in turn, shows the very subtle ways
in which our memories and thoughts can be influenced and altered, crucially
ways that we cannot easily detect. We are not talking about a case in which
someone witnesses an incident and after
having assisted at that incident he meets another witness who explicitly claims
that some details of the incident are different. We are talking about
information that has been indirectly suggested to the subjects and which has
the power to alter their initial memory of the incident.
Now you may
say that this is not so big deal: the students’ memories were a bit biased in
estimating the number of demonstrators by the fact that they were asked a
subsequent question misleading them in this respect. But what if such subsequent
questions can make us see things we never actually saw? This is what another
study by Loftus (1975, experiment 3) shows. In this study, participants saw a
clip about a car accident and were then asked ten questions about this
accident. As in the study described above, the participants were split in
groups of two, and each group was asked one question about a white car involved
in the accident that was different in the two groups. The first one was asked
“How fast was the white sports car going while traveling along the country
road?” but the second group was asked “How fast was the white sports car going
when it passed the barn while traveling along the country road?” This second
question, was based on a wrong presupposition, namely there was no barn
appearing in the film whatsoever. Participants of both groups filled-in a
second questionnaire one week later, asking them among others “Did you see a
barn?” Only 2.7% of the first group answered “yes” to that question, while a
17.3% of the second group that was asked the question presupposing the
existence of a barn reported having seen it. Although 17% is not a big
percentage in itself, again statistical analyses showed that this difference is
statistically significant: it is big enough to permit us to infer that the
second group was influenced in their answer by the false presupposition. This
result corroborates and extends the finding of the previous study. Here
participants were not simply biased in their answers by a false presupposition,
but were further lead to remember having seen a barn they actually had not. This
effect of a false presupposition on people’s memories is even more
consequential. Imagine for example this phenomenon occurring in a real-world
situation where witnesses are asked whether
they have seen the perpetrator’s weapon, in a case where the perpetrator did not actually have a weapon. The
results of the study just outlined suggest that this question has the potential
to make witnesses more likely to report having seen a weapon, while the poor
aggressor had not at all premeditated his action! The consequences for the
perpetrators sentence become obvious, highlighting the importance of the
malleability of memory in real-life contexts.
As to a
psychological aspect of the results of these studies, they are also interesting
in showing how our minds work. Participants watched an incident and they
afterwards received information that was implicitly transmitted to them,
through presuppositions. Crucially, these presuppositions seem able to enter
their memorial representations of the events that were initially formed based
on a visual stimulus, i.e. the clip they watched. So on the one hand, we have
the visual representation that their mind formed once while they watched the
incident. And on the other hand, we have information that is contained in a
linguistic stimulus that they process (the questions they were asked after
having watched the clip) which is integrated in the visually formed initial
representation. This process suggests how our mind can integrate pieces of
information that is linguistically transmitted to us, with information that we
acquire visually. For one, the ease with which such presuppositions can change
our visual memories show the power of language and the subtle ways it can be
used to influence our view of the world. The implications for real life
phenomena are, I believe, obvious…
Myrto Pantazi - Ph.D. student at the Université Libre de Bruxelles.
Reference
Loftus, E. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 560-572.
No comments:
Post a Comment